Self in Indian Philosophy

Self in Indian Philosophy
Self in Indian Philosophy

The human phenomenological experience of the universe consists fundamentally of the self or subject encountering a world of objects. Thus the two main objects of philosophy are the subject or the self—its nature and constitution—on the one hand, and the universe, along with its nature and constitution, on the other. Indian philosophy is no exception to this rule.

This experiencing self is referred to by several terms in Indian philosophy, the one most widely used being atman. The word is usually derived from the root an, which means “to breathe”; apparently the fact that the perceiving self is an animate being who faces other animate beings and inanimate objects is central to its emergence as the marker of the self.

It is called purua when its distinction from inanimate nature or prakti is emphasized, and it is called jiva when the atman is viewed as caught up in the cycle of sasara or birth and death, freedom from which becomes a goal of this empirical self (jiva). In many systems this freedom is attained when the jiva or empirical self discovers its true relationship to the atman or metaphysical self.

world of objects
world of objects

This is the essential theological structure of the school of Indian philosophy known as Vedanta. But virtually each school of Indian philosophy possesses its own conception of the self or atman, which must now be examined. Such an examination is facilitated by a review of the conception of the self in each of the nine schools of Indian thought.

Although this standardization is relatively recent it is worth employing because it enables one to present the concept of the self across the various schools with some measure of coherence. These nine schools, usually listed in order, are the Carvaka (of Lokayata), Jaina, Bauddha, Nyaya, Vaiseika, Sankhya, Yoga,Mimasa, and Vedanta.

Carvaka

According to the Carvaka school, the body itself constitutes the self (deha eva atma); of course, what is meant is that the conscious body constitutes the self.However, this immaterial element of consciousness in the body is considered an epiphenomenon of the material components of the body, in a manner reminiscent of scientific materialism.

Carvaka
Carvaka

The Carvaka school would establish the plausibility of the emergence of a property not contained in the elements by their coming together on the analogy of water, which possesses the quality of wetness, a property not possessed by the two gases of which it is composed.

There is no question then of postmortem survival according to this school, as consciousness perishes with death. It therefore emphasizes making the most of life, with a pleasant death serving as the counterpart of salvation. Thomas McEvilley (2002) notes that these doctrines are similar to the ones Plato attributes to the physiologoi.

Jaina

According to the Jaina school, the self consists of the soul or jiva which occupies the body. The soul is formless but it can occupy a body just as light might occupy a room. It is a striking feature of the Jaina view of the self that this jiva is said to be coextensive with the body.

Jaina
Jaina

In view of the fact that the soul occupies the body, it can be said to occupy space, as the body does, and may even be said to be capable of extension, as when the body grows. The whole range of existence, including plants and minerals along with insects and so on, possesses a conscious soul, and if such consciousness—which is characteristic of the soul—is not apparent, it is because it is dormant under the influence of karma.

In Jainism karma is considered a very fine material substance that can permeate a soul, just as motes of dust might permeate light. Jaina soteriology consists of ridding the jiva of such matter, which keeps it weighed down in sasara, so that, freed from it, it can rise to the top of the “universe” and be free forever.

According to Jainism, knowledge is the natural attribute of the atman, which is kept in check by ajiva or inanimate components of our being. “The eyes, for example are viewed here not as an aid to seeing, but as a check in the absolute sight of the soul” (Hiriyanna 1949, p. 61).

Bauddha

chamber of sasara
chamber of sasara

While the Carvaka school does not believe in an atman and denies anything like liberation, and the Jaina school believes in both, Buddhism denies the existence of a self or atman while upholding liberation from rebirth in the usual Indic sense.

According to Buddhism, continuity is possible without identity; hence there is no need to postulate a self that is reborn, for the next birth can be viewed as being caused by the present in the process of coming to an end, like an echo.

Nirvaña brings silence to the re-echoing chamber of sasara. The Buddhists seem to create many apparent logical difficulties for themselves by denying a permanent self or atman but according to them the other systems create their own existential problems by believing in one.

permanent substratum
permanent substratum

The Buddhist critique of a substantial ontology is very thoroughgoing; according to this critique, nothing whatsoever in this world possesses a permanent substratum (sabbe dhamma anatta). The permanence or lack of it in the self has been a major issue in the Hindu-Buddhist interface (Chakrabarti 1999, chapter 5, appendix).

Nyaya and vaiseika

The concepts of the self in the Nyaya and the Vaiseika schools have much in common and hence are presented together. According to the Nyaya and the Vaiseika school, the soul or atman is eternal, but consciousness is not its inherent property. Consciousness arises when the self or atman is conjoined with manas or the mind, which is, however, by itself inert.

The soul or atman differs from other atomic or all-pervasive objects in that, unlike them, it is potentially capable of consciousness. The selves are numerous and all-pervading but remain distinct in the state of release because of the property of visea, which accounts for things being different that are in other respects all alike—for example, two atoms that are otherwise identical are not numerically one.

Nyaya and vaiseika
Nyaya and vaiseika

The self has no consciousness in the state of release because such a state involves the absence of manas. The atman in Nyaya is a unique substance that possesses the attributes of cognition, emotion, and conation and the qualities of desire, aversion, pleasure, pain, volition, and knowledge.

The Vaiseika school provides a longer list (Organ). As these are not perceived by the external senses and are not physical, they must belong to a nonphysical substance such as the soul. However, although consciousness or knowledge is an attribute of the atman, it is not inseparable from it.

The soul is thus an independent substance, but consciousness is an accidental property of it. In order for conscious states to arise, manas must come into play, hence the otherwise cryptic remark that “the true self is broken up here, we may say, into two ‘selfless elements’” (Hiriyanna 1949, p. 91). Scholars such as McEvilley (2002) note parallels here with Aristotelian thought.

sankhya and yoga

sankhya and yoga
sankhya and yoga

The concepts of the self in the Sankhya and the Yoga schools are also sufficiently similar to be treated together. In Sankhya the self is called purua or soul and represents pure consciousness, in opposition to prakti, which represents matter.

The self loses its inherent consciousness by mistakenly identifying itself with the body as involved in the process of sasara; the self is utterly passive and merely a spectator but mistakes itself for an actor and thus undergoes the ups and downs of the cosmic drama. Although the word purua is often used in the singular, in reality the system allows for a plurality of puruas,all consisting of pure consciousness, but distinct from each other and prakti or matter.

The purua in Sakhya and Yoga is an uncaused, eternal, all-pervading, and changeless reality, which witnesses change as a transcendent subject distinguished by pure consciousness that can itself never become an object of knowledge. Salvation consists of this discrimination (viveka) that one is pure spirit and not the mind with whose derivative reality one identifies oneself.

totally independent
totally independent

The system of Yoga with its eight limbs or constituent elements is meant to guide one, through a series of meditations, to the realization of this ultimate transcendent witnessing subject as distinct from the mind, body, and ego just as the surface of the mirror is totally independent of the objects that are reflected in it but appear included in it.

Mimasa

The concept of the self in Mimasa is broadly similar to that found in Nyaya and Vaiseika, but there are some differences. The list of specific qualities characterizing the self is similar but not identical, with Mimasa dropping those of dharma and adharma and adding that of sakti or potency. The most significant difference however consists of the fact that while according to the Nyaya-Vaiseika school knowledge is a quality of the self, according to Mimasa it is an activity of the self.

Vedanta

The conception of the self or atman in Vedanta needs to be presented in accordance with the school of Vedanta involved—whether it is Advaita Vedanta, Visiadvaita Vedanta, or Dvaita Vedanta. Thus the exact conception of the atman depends on whether we are dealing with the “non-dualism of the qualified” (Advaita) or dualism (Dvaita).

Vedanta
Vedanta

Prior to identifying the self in these three schools of Vedanta, however, it might be useful to indicate the concept of the jiva they all share in common on the basis of their reliance on the same foundational texts.

Another aspect of the issues relating to the self or atman, which receives relatively greater treatment in Vedanta than in other systems, is its relationship to Brahman, or the ultimate reality. It will therefore be useful to begin the discussion of the self in the three Vedantic schools with the conception of it they all share and conclude it with their views on the nature of the relationship of this atman to Brahman.

The description of the human person as found in the Taittiriya Upanióad (II, 1–5) became paradigmatic in later Vedanta. According to this description a person consists of five sheaths within which the atman lies enclosed. Starting from the outside, the first sheath consists of the body made of food (annamaya-kosa); within it are the vital airs that comprise the second sheath (praamayakosa). The mind comprises the third sheath (manomaya kosa), consciousness the fourth (vijñanamaya kosa) and bliss the fifth (anandmaya).

ultimate reality
ultimate reality

In Advaita the self consists of self-effulgent consciousness (svaprakasa caitanya), which is rather than has consciousness. It is one and the same in all human subjects (unlike Sakhya) and eternally free. Later Vedanta also developed a doctrine of the three bodies that comprise a human being, which ostensibly seems to possess only one body.

These are the sthula-sarira (or gross body) which corresponds to the annamaya kosa; the sukma-sarira (or subtle body), which corresponds to the praamaya —the manomaya —and the vijñanamaya kosa and the karaa-sarira (or casual body), which corresponds to the anandamaya kosa. The true self—the atman —lies beyond all the five sheaths and the three bodies or may be said to constitute their nucleus depending on how one chooses to describe it (Kesarcodi-Watson 1994).

According to Advaita Vedanta, the atman is one’s true self and is identical with Brahman. Any differences between the two are adventitious, caused by upadhis or superimpositions. A popular metaphor illustrates the point as follows: Different jars of different shapes and sizes may contain jar-space.

sthula-sarira
sthula-sarira

The space enclosed by these jars may appear distinct, but if one breaks the jars, all space becomes one and the same. It was, however, one and the same to begin with—the jars only created ultimately artificial and unreal differences. Thus the selves of all are identical with each other and with Brahman.